Linguistics 522

Midterm Review

Trees
Chapter 5

Draw a tree for:

  1. Abelard wrote a poem with Heloise in mind.
      Right
      Also defensible (complement versus adjunct issue):

      One argument for the the idea that in mind is a complement of with (obligatoriness):

        Abelard wrote a poem with Heloise. (changes meaning)
      The following tree is wrong.
      Heloise in mind is not an NP.

      Arguments:

      1. * Heloise in mind kept him company. (Can't be a subject.)
      2. * It was [Heloise in mind] that Abelard wrote a poem with. (can't be preposed/clefted)
    1. The red volume of obscene verse from Italy
    2. The volume shocked the puritan soul of the minister with the beard quite throughly yesterday
        tree
Trees
Chap 6

  1. Spielberg believes the star to be a power-hungry dictator.
      The star was a power hungry dictator/The Tsar to be a power hungry dictator tree
      Spielberg believes CP. trees
      Spielberg believes the star to be a power-hungry dictator. tree
  2. John sold Mary's picture of the moon.
Binding
Theory
p. 99, (1)

For the following sentences, accept the given judgments. Explain whether the given judgment is predicted by the binding theory. For each example, discuss all principles that affect the coindexed NPs.

  1. * Fred i loves himi
      Predicted by Binding Theory. Principle B violation: A pronoun must be free in its binding domain; him is not free. It is bound by Fred, which is in the binding domain of him; that is, it is in the same clause.
  2. * Hei thinks that Sue loves Fredi
      Predicted by Binding Theory. Principle C violation: An R-Expression must be free. Fred is not free. It is bound by He. Note: There is no Principle B violation. The pronoun He is not bound. Although it is coindexed with Fred it is not C-commanded by Fred. Therefore it is not bound by Fred.
  3. * Michael'si father loves himselfi
      Predicted by Binding Theory. Principle A violation: An anaphor must be bound in its binding domain; himself is not bound. Although it is coindexed with Michael, it is not C-commanded by Michael.
      Therefore it is not bound by Fred. Note: In this sentence, Fred and himself are coindexed. Thus, this sentence represents the interpretation on which himself corefers with Fred. Therefore only the interpretation on which himself corefers with Fred is being ruled out.
  4. * Fred'si fatherj loves himj
      Predicted by Binding Theory. Principle B violation: A pronoun must be free in its binding domain; him is not free. It is bound by Fred's wife, which is in the binding domain of him; that is, it is in the same clause. (so this is really just like example (1)).
  5. * Susani thinks that John should marry herselfi.
      Predicted by Binding Theory. Principle A violation: An anaphor must be bound in its binding domain. Although herself is bound (it is coindexed with Susan, and C-commanded by Susan) it is not bound within its binding domain (its minimally containing clause).
  6. * John thinks that Susani should kiss heri.
      Predicted by Binding Theory. Principle B violation: A pronoun must be free in its binding domain; her is not free. It is bound by Susan, which is in the binding domain of her; that is, it is in the same clause.
  7. * I spoke to himi in Beni's office.
Not Predicted by Binding Theory. Examining the tree for this sentence we see that him does not C-command Ben. Therefore, despite the co-indexing, him does not bind Ben. Therefore, Ben is free and there is no Principle C violation, so the impossibility of co-reference here is not predicted by the Binding Theory.
Anaphora
and replacement
 

A syntax tree is a notation for writing down claims about a sentence or phrase. This .problem is about the claims that trees make about how anaphoric elements should behave.

  1. On the basis of our assumptions about the anaphoric element one, which part or parts of the Noun Phrase a World War I collection of poems does the following tree claim can be replaced by one? [Make sure your answer is complete. If there is more than one part of the phrase that should be replaceable by one according to the tree, list multiple parts. However, you do not need to consider the internal structure of phrases that are represented by triangles.]
  2. On the basis of our assumptions about the anaphoric element one, which part or parts of the Noun Phrase a World War I collection of poems does the following tree claim can be replaced by one?
  3. Now construct some examples that argue for one tree and against the other based on the actual observed behavior of one.

Summary of results:

  1. The basic assumption:
    Anaphoric elements replace constituents
  2. one replaces N-bars.
  3. If a PP is attached as a complement its sister is not an Nbar and can NOT be replaced by one.

Other anaphoric elements:

Do so: replaces Vbars
John put a rug in the washer and Sue did so too. [Replaces put a rug in the washer]
* John put a rug in the washer and Sue did so in the sink.
Does this argue that in the washer is a complement or an adjunct?
VP-ellipsis: Empty string replaces VP
John put a rug in the washer and Sue did too.
* John put a rug in the washer and Sue did in the sink.
Who might be going to the cinema on Tuesday?
John might be. [∅ = going to the cinema on Tuesday.]
John might. [∅ = be going to the cinema on Tuesday.]
John might on Wednesday. [∅ = be going to the cinema]
John might be on Wednesday. [∅ = going to the cinema]
so: replaces Abars
John is very fond of Mary in some ways, but less so in others [so = fond of Mary]
John is very fond of Mary, but less so of Jean [so = fond]
so: replaces Pbars
John is always at odds with his colleagues, but he is less so with his friends. [so = at odds]
Theta
Criterion
 

Evaluate this claim: the following sentence under the indicated coindexing, is a theta-criterion violation.

  1. Johni believes that hei is a genius.
Justification: One guy, John, has 2 theta roles. True or False?

False. Read theta-criterion (p. 171)

  1. Each argument is assigned one and only one theta role.
  2. Each theta role is assigned to one and only one argument.
Restating (more explicitly)
  1. Each argument position of a predicate is assigned one and only one theta role.by the predicate
  2. Each theta role of a predicate is assigned to one and only one argument of the predicate.

Important:

    The theta-criterion constrains the relationship between theta roles and syntactic constituents that fill argument positions of a predicate.
John is not a syntactic constituent. He is an entity in the world. The theta criterion does not prevent John from bearing two theta roles.

Claim: (1) is still a theta-criterion violation. The NPs John and he fill the same theta role for the predicate is. And also for the predicate thinks. True or false?

False again. The theta criterion is about subjects and complements of a predicate. It requires that all of a predicate's theta roles be used up by the subject and complements of the predicate, and that the subject and complements all receive theta roles. John is the subject of the predicate thinks. Thus the theta-criterion requires that thinks assign John one and only one theta role. It does:

    think: NPi [ __ CP[-Que,+Fin]j]
    experiencer proposition
    i j
In the downstairs clause, the verb be assigns he exactly one theta role.
    be: NPi [ ___ NPj]
    theme goal
    i j

Observations:

  1. The Theta-criterion does not preclude coreference between NP arguments, even between arguments in the same clause. But each NP must receive its own theta role from the predicate that it is an argument of. Thus NPs in separate clauses must receive tehta roles from separate predicates.
  2. The theta criterion does preclude a predicate from assigning theta roles to NPs other than its OWN subject and complements. For example, a verb may not assign roles to NPs in another clause.
  3. The theta criterion is not only about verbs. It is about ANY head and its complements and/or subject.
    1. * The book of poetry of prose
    2. * John is fond of Mary of Sue.
    We have claimed that complements cannot in general be repeated. Our formal theoretical explanation for this is now the theta-criterion.
  4. The theta criterion is not only about NPs It is about ANY complements and/or subject.
    1. John thinks [CP that Mary is a genius.]
    2. [CP That Mary is a genius] is obvious.
    Both the subject and object CPs in (1) and (2) require propositional roles from their respective predicates, according to the theta criterion.
  5. There is an exemption for subject position. Roleless expletives occur in subject position, inserted between D-structure, where the theta-criterion applies, and the surface, where the Extended Projection Principle applies.
      obvious: [ __ CP[-QUE,+FIN]i ]
      proposition
      i
    1. It is obvious that Mary is a genius.
    2. * That Mary is a genius is obvious that John is a genius.
    3. That he married Mary proves that John is a genius.
    Because it is inserted late, the expletive it is exempted from the theta criterion. Neither CP that Mary is a genius in (2) can be inserted inserted late, so the Θ-criterion still applies. Thus CPs can occur with predicates that assign appropriate propositional roles. (2) here is a theta-criterion violation because there are two CPs, neither of which can function as roleless expletive, and obvious has only one proposition role to assign. In contrast (3) incurs no violation because prove has two distinct propositional roles.
      prove: CP[-QUE,+FIN]i [ __ CP[-QUE,+FIN]j ]
      proposition, source proposition, theme
      i j
  6. Prepositional phrase complements. Roles are assigned to directly to the ``referents'' of DP/NPs and CPs. In contrast, with PP complements, roles are assigned to the objects of the preposition:
    1. John gave the book to Mary.
        give: NPi [ __ NPj [PP to NPk]]
        agent theme goal
        i j k
    2. Optionality. The theta criterion requires to posit separate lexical entries in those quite common cases where a complement is optional:
      1. John ate the apple.
      2. John ate
      The entry for the first sentence is:
        eat: NPi [ __ NPj]
        agent theme
        i j
      Unless there is a second lexical entry for eat in which the theme role is missing, the second sentence would have to be a theta criterion vioation.

      The entry for the second sentence would look like this:

        eat: NPi [ __ ]
        agent
        i
Verb
Particles
  We review constituency arguments by reviewing the case of verb particles.
(1) John turned off the stove.
The question we will address is: Is the italicized word string a constituent?

Constituency arguments:

(2) *It was off the stove John turned. [with the meaning: John extinguished the stive light.]
Movement by clefting does not work: Evidence against constituency
(3a) * Off which stove did John turn?
(3b) * The stove off which John turned was very old. [Compare: The shelf off which John took the book was very high.]
(3c) The stove which John turned off was very old.
Movement for question formation and relative clause formation does not work: Evidence against constituency.
(4a) * John turned off the stove and on the lamp.
(4b) The cat climbed off the stove and under the table.
Conjunction with similar word sequences in (4a) does not work: Evidence against constituency. Contrast (4b), where arguably two PPs are being conjoined.

The do-so and VP deletion tests do not help us here, because they will only establish the constituency of VPs.

(5)
-- What did John turn off?
-- * Off the stove?
Off the stove cannot occur as an isolated fragment, which argues against its constituency.

There is one other important argument which is not really a constituency argument. Passsivization is possible from the site after off:

(6) The stove was turned off by John,
Normally only the NP directly following the Verb can be passivized. This peculiar fact could be explained if we assume the structure is:
Theta grids  

Identify the violations of the theta criterion in the following ungrammatical sentences, if any. If you claim the theta-criterion is not responsible for the ungrammaticality, you are hereby invited to speculate on what is:

  1. * John arrived in Boston on Monday on Tuesday.
  2. * John kicked that Bill was laughing.
  3. * Sue love for Harry to leave.
  4. * John thinks that left.
  5. * Sue devoured.
  6. * was obvious that the Theta-criterion had been violated.
  1. * John arrived in Boston on Monday on Tuesday.
    No. Theta criterion does not apply to adjuncts. Problem is semantic.
  2. * John kicked that Bill was laughing.
    Yes. There is no second theta role for kick appropriate for a proposition.
  3. * Sue love for Harry to leave.
    No. Problem is lack of tensed or agreeing verb.
  4. * John thinks that left.
    Yes. left assigns a theta role to an external argument, which is missing.
  5. * Sue devoured.
    Yes. Devour assigns a theta role to an internal argument, which is missing.
  6. * was obvious that the Theta-criterion had been violated.
    No, it wasn't. Violates the Extended projection principle, which requires all clauses to have subjects.