Linguistics 522
The Lexicon
Lecture 7
The Lexicon, The Theta-Criterion,
and the Extended Projection Principle
Subcategorization revisited
Information in a lex entry:
devour
- John devoured the steak.
- * John devoured.
- * John devoured at/of/to the steak
devour:
[+V,-N]
[NP]
Phonological Info:
Category (Radford uses features)
Subcategorization frame
A Permissible tree for devour
|
Lexical Examples
rely
- John relies on Mary.
- * John relies.
- * John relies Mary.
- * John relies to/at/for Mary
rely:
[+V,-N]
[PP]
where PP must be headed by on
Info about what preposition specifically is used is not
included.
donate
- John donated money to the orphanage.
- * John donated to the orphanage.
- John donated no money to any one.
donate:
[+V,-N]
[NP,PP]
(where PP must be headed by on)
expect
- John expects Mary to leave.
- John expects Mary. (different meaning)
- John expects an earthquake. (same meaning as 2?)
- John expects there to be an earthquake. (evidence for exceptional S)
- John expects advantage to be taken of the students.(evidence for exc. S)
- Paraphrse relation (evidence for exc S)
John expects the doctor to examine Mary.
John expects Mary to be examined by the doctor.
expect1
[+V,-N]
[NP]
expect2
[+V,-N]
[S]
A Permissible tree for expect1
|
A Permissible tree for expect2
|
afraid
- John is afraid of Mary.
- * John is afraid to leave.
- * There is afraid to be an earthquake.
- * Advantage is afraid to be taken of Mary.
afraid1:
[+V,+N]
[PP]
where PP must be headed by of
afraid1:
[+V,+N]
[S']
where the Comp of S' must be [-FIN,-WH]
Thematic Relations
Agent:
- John smashed the banana.
- John up the hill.
- John hit the ball over the fence,
Theme:
- John smashed the banana.
- The banana broke
Locative: In the room
Source: from Mary, from the room
Goal: To Mary, To the room.
Projection and Theta-Marking
What are Thematic Relations?
Answer: The relations the participants of the
action (or more generally) situation
described by the predicate
bear the to the situation, relations
such as being an active agent, being a cause,
being the source from which motion
or energy begins.
Objection: But there are many such relations
and each participant bears many of
them. How do we know which ones
are important?
|
|
Why do we introduce Theta-roles?
Answer: It turns out thast the notion
of a thematic relation, while useful,
is raises many issues we do not
need to deal with as syntacticians.
What we really care about is not what the
exact thematic relations are or
how many
of them there are, but just
that fact that there is a unique
cluster of relations for each argument.
We call that cluster of relations
that makes each participant different from
the others the participants
theta-role.
Thus the claim is not that there is a unique relation
chosen from some special set that each participant
bears but that there is a set
of relations uniquely identifying each
participant.
|
|
Even when we have a verb where two participants
seem to be doing the same thing, there
always turns out to be some subtle difference
on closer inspection:
- The car collided with the truck.
- The car and the truck collided. (paraphrases [1], car and truck bear same thematic roles?)
- The car collided with the lamp post.
- ? The car and the lamp post collided. (does not paraphrase [3])
The following principle formalizes this idea.
Theta Criterion
Each argument bears one and only
one theta role, and each
theta role is assigned to only
one argument.
|
And here is the principle we will use to hook this
idea up to the syntax:
Projection Principle
Syntactic Representations must be projected from the lexicon,
in that they observe the lexical properties of the items they contain.
|
The things we have been doing can be viewed as implementations of
these principles
- Subcategorization frames are determined
(or at least constrained) by semantic properties.(Theta criterion)
- Verbs must enter trees compatible with their
subcat frames (Projection P)
- No syntactic process can add or subtract arguments.
(What about passive? Causatives in languages that have them)
Two examples:
- Exceptional clauses:
John expects Mary to go.
What the data tells us: Mary bears no semantic role
with respect to expect. Mary bears a semantic role
with respect to go.
What the theta criterion tells us:
Mary cannot be an argument of expect.
Mary must be an argument of go.
What the projection principle tells us:
The syntactic position
the NP Mary occupies cannot be
subcategorized for by expect
in the lexicon.
The NP Mary must occupy
the subject position for go
(in order to be assigned a role
by go).
Conclusion:
The structure must look like this:
[V' [V expect ]
[ S [NP Mary ] [I to ]
[VP go]]]
- Control Verbs:
John persuaded Mary to go.
What the data tells us: Mary bears a semantic role
with respect to persuade. Mary bears a semantic role
with respect to go.
What the theta criterion tells us:
Mary must be an argument of persuade.
Mary must be an argument of go.
But it also tells us no NP can receive two roles.
Therefore there must be two NPs, one of which
is empty.
What the projection principle tells us:
The syntactic position
the NP Mary occupies must be
subcategorized for by persuade
in the lexicon.
The empty NP Mary controls must occupy
the subject position for go
(in order to be assigned a role
by go).
Conclusion:
The structure must look like this:
[V' [V persuade ] [NP Mary ]
[ S' [Comp e ] [S [NP PRO ] [I to ]
[VP go]]]]
The Lexicon: What it is
- Lexical Entries
- Lexical Redundancy Rules
For example:
Redundancy rules make predictions about subcategorization from meaning:
Examples:
- Whether a head takes an interrogative complements (+WH) or not:
interrogative and dubitative predicates do. (
know, wonder, find out, realize, wonder, inquire, ask)
- Desiderative and emotive predicates take
infinitival complements (-FIN) ( prefer, aim, dying(adj),
astound, want, hate, love, etc )
- Cognitive and assertive predicates
take finite(+FIN) declarative(-WH) clauses
- Exceptional clauses go with cognitive
or assertive verbs (know, believe, imagine, declare,
report)
Note: You do not have to remember any of these terms
for classifying predicates. Just be familiar
with the idea that certain subcategorization
properties are semantically predictable.
Other examples of principles predicting information,
which therefore need not be listed in the lexicon
or in phrase structure ruiles
- Strict adjacency: An NP complement must be adjacent to its head.
- Periphery Principle: Heads occur at the periphery of X-bar
- Head First Principle: Heads precede complements
Syntactic Principles About Clausal Complements
- Interrogative clauses are Sbars (eithe rifnite or nonfinite).
Therefore no interrogtaive exceptional clauses (=S not Sbar).
Or small clauses.
- A non-finite clause with an overt subject must have an overt
complementizer.
I'm dying for/*e you to do it.
- A non-finite clause with a PRO subject requires an
empty complementizer.
I'm dying *for/e to do it.
- There is a class of verbs
taking nonfinite complements
which permits explicit for complementizers
(and there is a class which does not):
- I would prefer/like/hope for you to go.
- Harry dared/attempted *for her/e to go.
- Exceptional clauses and small clauses must immediately
follow their heads.
- It follows that there are no verbs foo
that would fit in the following frame
* I fooed Mary [SJohn to go.]
Though there are transitive verbs which take SBar
complements:
I signalled Mary for John to go.
- There are 4 types of small clauses
which may be indvidually subcategorized for
(p. 359): AC (adjectival), PC (prepositional),
NC (nomial), and VC (verbal). Within VC we have
the null, -en, and -ing types (61 d,e,f).
Syntactic Principles About Other Complements
- Nouns and Adjectives take
the full range of complements
but do not take NP complements,
small clause or exceptional clause
complements:
- Rome's destruction of/*e the city
- Fred's belief that John would go
- * Fred's belief of John to go
- * The Parliament's election of him king
- Prepositions take
the full range of complements
including small clause and finite clausal complements,
but do not allow that:
- since the party
- since *that/e Mary left
- until the party
- until *that/e Mary left
- *while the party
- while *that/e Mary partied
- Mary's turned on by [SC John Wayne on a horse ]