Linguistics 522
Lecture 5
X-Bar Syntax
Phrase-structure rules: Complements, Specifiers, and adjuncts
Much of our energy last time expended on motivating a constituent
intermediate between N and N'' in NPs. That was N'.
We argued that there were two sorts of Noun modifiers that
could attach to a nominal
constituent to make up an N', complements and adjuncts.
We argued that that when you attached a D (determiner) to an N',
that made it an N''.
Now we argue analagously for AP, VP, and PP.
- We argue that there are constituents intermediate between the
heads and full phrases in AP, VP, and PP. These are A', V', and P',
respectively.
- We argue for the complement/adjunct distinction in V'. What about
the others?
- We argue for something analagous to D in N'', something that
added to A', V', P' makes a A'', V'', P''.
X-Bar Syntax
|
|
Stated in terms the phrase-structure rules we have been using till now,
we have sets of PS rules, all with analogous structures:
-
- A'' => Spec A'
- A' => A' Adjunct
- A' => A Complement
-
- V'' => Spec V'
- V' => V' Adjunct
- V' => V Complement
-
- P'' => Spec P'
- P' => P' Adjunct
- P' => P Complement
We use Spec (for Specifier) for the constituent added to the single bar
level category to make t he double-bar level.
Using X to stand for ANY of the major categories, the pattern is
this:
- [X'' Spec [X' [X' X Complement] Adjunct]]
Voila. X-Bar syntax.
|
Specifiers,
complements
and adjuncts
|
|
- Specifiers italicized:
- AP: how proud of her son was she?
- PP: right under the bridge is where you'll find it.
- VP: She must be thinking of you.
- Complements italicized:
- AP: How proud of her son was she?
- PP: Right under the bridge is where you'll find it.
- VP: She must be thinking of you.
- The only obligatory element of a phrase (generally)
is the lexical head. Phrases withOUT complements or specifiers;
- NP: Students rose in protest,
- AP: She was proud.
- PP: She went in,
- VP: She must think.
|
Subcategorization
|
|
We use the term subcategorization to denote the kind
of complement a category takes as complement. We have seen that
verbs can subcategorize NP (transitive verbs), PP, AP, and S.
- John devoured the trout.
- John despaired of an answer.
- Mary seemed kind.
- Mary proved that she was inoocent.
We note in passing that some verbs subcategorize V' (not V'' or V):
- I saw John run down the road.
- *I saw John be running down the road.
- *I saw John have finished his work.
|
Arguments for V Complement versus adjunct distinction
Preposing
|
Preposing test. Adjuncts prepose easily.
- He decided on the boat. (ambiguous)
- On the boat, he decided. (one reading)
- He explained last night.(ambiguous)
- Last night he explained. (one reading)
- He laughed at the clown. (complement)
- He laughed at the office. (adjunct)
- *At the clown he laughed. (complement)
- At the office he laughed. (adjunct)
- He worked at the office. (adjunct)
- He worked at physics. (complement)
- At the office he worked. (adjunct)
- *At physics he worked. (different reading)
|
Pseudo-passive
|
Only complements may pseudo-passivize:
- Physics needs to be worked at.
- *The office was worked at. (If office is the place where work happened)
- The clown was laughed at.
- *The office was laughed at. (If office is the place where laughter happened).
- The boat was decided on after lengthy deliberation. (no reading on which
the boat is the place where trhe deciding happened)
- Last night couldn't be explained by anyone. (No reading on which
last night
is the time at which something (else) was explained.
|
Do-so anaphora
|
It appears that do so anaphora is to wo V-bars what
one-anaphora is to N-bars. That is, do so takes V' antecedents:
- John will buy the book on Tuesday and Ringo will do so on Wednesday.
- * John will put the book on the table and Ringo will do so on the chair.
|
Order facts
|
As we expect from our X-bar rules, complements must precede adjuncts
- He worked physics at the office.
- * He worked at the office at physics.
- He laughed at the clown at ten o clock.
- * He laughed at ten o clock at the clown.
|
Syntactic
(not semantic)
selection
|
Semantics may decide what adjuncts go with what heads. But
it isn't enough to decide what complements go with what heads.
We need to allow for arbitrary syntactic selection.
- He asked the man next door what time it was.
- * He asked of the man next door what time it was.
- * He inquired the man next door whether he was leaving.
- He inquired of the man next door whether he was leaving.
- He desired justice.
- * He desired for justice.
- * He longed justice.
- He longed for justice.
- Mary's desire for justice was well-known.
Note that the verb desire requires an NP complement.
But this doesn't seem to be a semantic fact because the
semantically closely related verb long
and noun desire both
require PP complements with for.
So if you have a modifier
that is acceptable with one head but not another semantically
close head, that is evidence that the modifier is a complement.
|
Obligatoriness
|
Adjuncts are never obligatory.
- John treated Mary badly.
- John treated Mary. (different meaning)
To keep the interpretretaion of treat meaning
behaved towards we need to include an adverb like
well, or badly.
This is evidence that badly is a complement of treat.
|
Ellipsis
|
Verb phrase Ellipsis ellides V-bars or V-double bars.
- Who might be going to the cinema when?
- John might be on Tuesday.
- Who will put the book where?
- * John will on the table.
- Who might have gone to the cinema when?
- John might have last night.
(4) is an attempt to ellide a non-constituent
put the book, which is
only a part of a V', and is therefore ungrammatical.
|
Emphatic
reflexives
|
Let's assume emphatic reflexives like this:
- John baked the cake himself.
are adjuncts
Does this predict the following facts?
- John will bake the cake himself for the party.
- John will bake the cake for the party himself.
- John will put the candles on the cake himself.
- *John will put the candles himself on the cake.
Answer: Yes. Why?
|
Structure of AP
Basic
Pattern |
[AP> (D) A (Complement) Adjunct*]
|
Determiners
|
- It's hard to believe he's that angry.
- It's hard to believe he's so angry.
- She was very angry.
- She was much kinder to John.
- He was too tall.
- How tall was she?
- She was as tall as John.
- She was a foot taller than John.
- She was a foot taller than John.
- He was more impressive close up.
- She acted quite independently.
Recall that the category A includes both adverbs and adjectives.
There are specifiers of both |
Complements |
We assume complements are introduced by the following
PS rules:
A' => A (PP)
A' => A (S)
A' => A (V')
Crucially, complements are sisters of A, not A'.
Here are some examples:
- He is fond of Mary.
- He is proud of Mary.
- She is angry at John.
- She was kind to John.
- She is happy that he would show up.
- She is eager to run marathons.
- She made up her mind independently of me.
Note that adverbs, too, may have complements.
|
The A'' constituent
|
The rules above embody the assumption that there
is a constituent A'' that includes a head
adjective and ALL its modifiers,
complements, heads, and adjuncts alike.
A key argument for this constituent:
- Preposing
Fond of Mary though he is in some ways
|
The A' constituent
|
The rules above embody the assumption that there
is a constituent of A'' which excludes the
determiner and includes both the the head and its
complement and adjunct modifiers. We call this constituent
A'.
Some arguments motivating this constituent:
- Anaphora
- John is very fond of Mary in some ways, but he is less
so in other ways.D[so = [A' very fond of Mary])
- John used to be very fond of Mary in some ways but he is rapidly
becoming less so. (so = [A' very fond of Mary in some ways])
- Coordination
- John is very rich and thin.
- The pole is very long and thin.
- John is very proud of Mary and beholden to her.
|
Adjuncts
|
There are two types of adjuncts
- Attribute adjuncts
She severely critical of the president
- Postadjectival adjuncts
He is fond of Mary in some ways
We assume these are introduced by the following rules:
- A' => ADVP A' [attributive adjunct]
- A' => A' ADVP
- A' => A' PP
Crucially all adjuncts are sisters of A' and are introduced
by recursive rules.
|
Arguments distinguishing A Complements from A adjuncts
Obligatoriness
|
Obligatory modifers, we assume, are complements. Why this is natural will be
clearer later when we flesh out our theory of
the lexicon.
|
Coordination |
Complements conjoin with complements, adjuncts with adjuncts, and the
twain shall never meet. This follows if we assume a conjunction rule
something like:
The data:
- John is fond of Mary and of Sue.
- John was utterly and completely foolish.
- *John is fond of Mary and in some ways.
<
Note that this test has to be taken with a grain of salt,
beacuse there are strong constraints even on the coordination of adjuncts:
*She was fond of Mary in some ways
|
Iterability
|
The rules introducing complements and adjunct predict
complements do not iterate and adjuncts do:
K
She was severely directly critical of the president
*She was proud of Mary of John
|
Order |
The rules introducing complements and adjuncts
predict that complements must come
closer to the head adjective:
She is fond of Mary in some ways
? She is fond in some ways of Mary
|
Proform |
We assume so can take only A's (not As) as its antecednt.
- John is very fond of Mary in some ways, but he is less
so in other ways.D[so = [A' very fond of Mary])
- John used to be very fond of Mary in some ways but he is rapidly
becoming less so. (so = [A' very fond of Mary in some ways])
- * Jean is very fond of Mary but she is less so of John.
(so = [A fond], which contradicts our assumption
that the antecedent of so is always an A')
If your grammaticality judgements do not in fact make the last
example ungrammatical, then so anaphora does not
provide a testr distinguishing A complements from
A adjuncts (although it still gives us evidence motivating
the A' constituent). m We must also revise
our description of so as a Pro-A.
so. takes either A' or As as its antecedents.
|
Arguments for specifier vs. adjunct analysis
Note that a lot of things we've called A' specifiers
are sometimes called
adverbs:
so,that,very,how,too, how
But so are many of the things we've called attributive adjuncts.
How do we tell them apart?
In general specifiers according to our rules can't iterate:
In some cases they may appear to:
But in this cases, we assume the first very is
a specifier of the second very. The
second very, then,
is a specified specifier.
But this makes iterability hard to use as negative test.
If something iterates to the left of a head,
we may always call it a specified specifier.
Still, if something fails to iterate, we've
got good evidence it should be a specifier:
* He was two feet a head taller than John.
A weird fact about many A' specifiers is that many of them
cause a funny kind of preposing of AP out of NPs:
- They chose so large a milkshake that they couldn't finish it
- I couldn't believe they chose that large a milkshake.
- How large a milkshake do you want?
Instead of occuring after the determiner as attributive APs usually
do these, these APs occur before it.
Not all do:
- * They chose very large a milkshake.
But it's a good positive indicator. Preposing out of NP
indicates specifier-hood.
P'' and its specifiers, complements and adjuncts
Our PP modifers will look a lot like our modifiers
for other categories.
- [P'' (Spec) Head (Complement) Adjunct*]
We assume phrase structure rules analogous to those above:
- P'' => (D) P'
- P' => ADVP P' [attributive adjunct]
- P' => P' ADVP
- P' => P' PP
- P' => P S
- P' => P NP
- P' => P PP
- P' => P
Examples that Radford discusses (with some fleshing out):
- Complements
- NP prepositional objects
- during the war
- before the war
- Sentential complements (subordinating conjunctions
as prepositions)
- before the war ended
- when Sam arrived
- prepositional phrase complements
- out from under the table
- out of toilet paper
- away from Boston
- Specifiers
- right under the textbook
- less at odds with his friends
- so completely in the wrong [these example discussed
further below]
- two years before the war
- The bodyguards stood quite close behind him.
- The rabbit burrowed quite deep under the surface
- Adjuncts
- prepositional adjuncts
- at odds with his friends
- out of touch in some ways
- the man in the park on Tuesday
- attribute adjuncts
- completely at odds with his friends
- completely in the wrong
- partly out of the drawer
There is another analysis available for
- so completely in the wrong
So could be a specifier of completely
rather than of the preposition. Our rules allow both
and both seem semantically possible.[Draw
the alternative tree, Radford's is on p. 77] Radford notices
this systematic
spoecifier ambiguity
in earlier chapters, but doesn't fully
address the problem.
Notice we need so as a specifier
of completely independently:
Notice that both analyses account for the word
order facts Radford cites.
- * completely so in the wrong
Arguments that something is a P modifier
PP modifiers often occur in positions where they
could be interpeted as modifying something else, for
example whatever the PP is modifying. In such
cases, we need ways to argue
that a modifier really is a modifier for the PP,
and not something else. For example,
consider in some ways in
He's out of touch in some ways.
How do we know that in some ways isn't modifying
the copula is instead of the preposition?
Or in
The man in the park on Tuesday
How do we know on Tuesday isn't modifying
the noun man?
Here's an argument.
Call this a semantic dependency argument: The modifier's presence
depends on the preposition's presence:
- He's out of touch in some ways
- ? He is in some ways.
- The man in the park on Tuesday was a policeman.
- ? The man on Tuesday was a policeman.
Arguments for complement vs. adjunct analysis for
Prepositions
Obligatoriness
|
Obligatory modifers are complements.
- Lay the strip along the side of the drawer.
- * Lay the strip along.
- They were always at odds with their friends.
- They were always at odds
|
Iterability
|
The rules introducing complements and adjunct predict
complements do not iterate and adjuncts do:
He was at odds with his friends in some ways
* He was at odds at loggerheads.
|
Order |
The rules introducing complements and adjuncts
predict that complements must come
closer to the head adjective:
He was at odds with his friends in some ways.
He was at odds in some ways with his friends.
He was so out of touch in some ways.
* He was so out in some ways of touch.
|
Proform |
We assume so can take only P's (not Ps) as its antecedent.
- I know that he's at odds with his colleagues, but he's less
so with his friends.(so = [P'at odds])
- * I know that he's at odds with John, but he's less
so odds with Mary.(so = [Pat])
This time the judgements
on the so test seem much more
robust. Interesting.
|
Arguments for specifier versus head
- The dispute dates from before the war.[HEAD]
- I've put your book over in the corner.[SPECIFIER]
Obligatoriness |
 
|
- * The dispute dates before the war.[from omitted]
- Put your books in the corner.[over omitted]
We've seen that specifiers can be optional. But heads
determine the distributional properties of their phrases.
They are not optional.
Note that using obligatoriness to argue
that something is not a specifier
has to be done with caution. We argued in class that
the italicized constituent was a specifier:
- He put the book six inches from the
end of the table
- He put the book from the end of the table.
Note that in this context the specifier is obligatory. Sometiems
specifiers are obligatory. We saw this in the case of
NP specifiers:
- The man was awake.
- * Man was awake.
|
Subcategorization |
 
|
We see that the same verb date syntactically
selects a PP headed by from.
The dispute dates from the time of the war.
This motivates calling the head of
from before the war from as well in the
previous example.
|
Complement-taking |
 
|
Over takes complements of its own, Radford argues, as in:
- I've put your books over there in the corner.
If there is a complement of over, then in the corner
can't also be.
This argument has several flaws. First, we know heads can take
two complements,as give does. Second, the so-called
head in the previous example is Optional:
- I've put your books there in the corner.
What this suggests is that over in over there
is a specifier of there, which is why it is optional.
|
General Issues
So far we allow recursive modifiers to attach only to
X' constituents.
Radford discusses the possibility that
there are recursive modifiers of X and of X''. He suggests
words like even as an N'' modifier
and enough as an A modifier and our famous verb
particles as V modifiers:
- She certainly looks tall enough.
- Even an idiot can do X-bar Theory.
- She turned down the bed.
A disappointment for this analysis is that none of these is
recursive:
- * She certainly looks tall enough enough.
- * Even even an idiot can do X-bar Theory.
- * She turned down down the bed.
Rule Constraints
We continue to write PS-rules as we have, reemembering that
our category names are really abbreviations for sets
of features.
We formalize X-bar theory as a set
of constraints on Rules. We call the intervening
bar-levels between lexical X and the highest
level X projections of X. We call the
highest-level projection the
maximal projection of X.
- Endocentricity constraint(EC): The output of a rule must
contain a category of the same category and either of
the same bar level or lower.
- Modifier maximality constraint(MMC): All the nonheads
in a rule must be maximal projexctions (X-double bar
categories:Stowell).
Radford observes that the MMC requires us to revise:
to be
Which seems right:
- How many students are there?
- How many more students are there?
- There are three times as many students as there used to be.
Eliminating categorial rules
The gist of this is that we move to very general rules
like this complement rule
We now allow any kind of complement and any number of
them with any category head,
overgenearting wildly.
We make the same move for all the rules,
leaving ourselves with the problem of explaining
why the rules overgenerate, for example, accounting
for why adjectives, adverbs, and nouns never
take NP complements.