Intension A theoretical Construct |
  |
Solution: We're going to extend the way we use the term denotation by means of a theoretical construct. Consider dog. At any instant of time there is a certain set of individuals that is the set of dogs. If the world were only slightly different than it is, there would be a slightly different set of dogs. Thus the denotation depends not only on the sense but also on the way the world is, or as we shall say, on what world we are in. So our theoretical construct is this: there is a set of worlds we call the set all possible worlds, and the denotation of dog varies from world to world:
So denotations are double-layered. A denotation is an intension that picks out an extension at each possible world. These examples are incomplete. The set of all possible worlds really needs to cover all possible ways the world might differ from the way it is. With respect to the word dog the set of possible worlds needs to provide with all possible individuals that might be a dog, and at least one world for each distinct possible set of dogs. That's a lot of worlds.... |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Denotation Extension |
Last week I was basically using sense as a synonym of meaning and denotation as a synonym for extension. I did not talk about intension, because I want to reserve that term for the technical notion just introduced. A theoretical construct. So let's talk about intensions and extensions for sentences now |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Extensions for sentences |
  |
Last week, we looked at TWO ANSWERS to this question:
This week we focus on Frege's answer, as our textbook does. To answer this question we will return to the principle of substitutivity of identicals. A sentence is a complex expression with a denotation. Let's see what happens when we substitute different expressions with the same denotation into it:
But what is it that is the same? Not the meaning. In a different world in which the same guy wasn't Mr Universe 1970 and the governor of California 2005, these sentences might have different truth-values. But the meaning would still be the same. But here is the key point: Since denotations of
So it is the truth-value of a sentence that functions like a denotation . It is the truth-value of a sentence that stays the same when expressions with identical denotations are substituted into it. [Frege's argument] So For Frege the extension of a sentence will be a truth-value (either true or false); and the intension will be a table that tells us the truth value in each world. The extension at each world will depend on the extension of expressions inside it at that world. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Example: Intensions |
  |
And suppose that this is the way it is with grinning in our 4 worlds:
And consistent with these we have the following intension:
Note: I differ slightly from the text in saying that intension of a sentence is a table giving the truth value at each world. The text just says the intension of a sentence is the set of possible worlds at which the sentence is true. These ideas are equivalent: You can construct the table from the set, and vice versa. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Sentence Meaning |
  |
The wrong theory: the meanings of the words determine the meaning of a sentence. Problem:
Pick from among the following nouns for A,B,C:
Pick from among the following transitive verbs for X,Y.
Many sentences with MANY different meanings:
Sentence Meaning = Lexical Meaning + Structural Meaning This is the same point I made last week with the example of intersection semantics (only the words in the sentence mattered in that theory and that theory was wrong). |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
A job for Syntax |
  |
Determine structural meaning! That's what it's for. That's why there IS such a thing as syntax! You finally know. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Compositional Semantics |
  |
A compositional semantics for a (fragment of a) language is a formal account of how the meaning of the whole is composed of the meaning of the parts. Given what we just noted about structural meaning, this means that a compositional semantics combines lexical meaning and structural meaning to compute the meaning of sentences. It does this by providing rules for interpreting strcutures. More technically, we have just committed to an intensional theory. Thus our theory needs to account for how the intension of the whole is composed out of the intension of the parts. But in working out the details, it quickly becomes clear that not every word has a natural intension:
For example, the extensional rule for and (discussed in Section 1.3.4, (38), (39)) is:
Thus, all the rule has to do is tell us under what circumstances the sentences is true or false (in terms of the truth values of the sentence's parts). A similar rule for or:
The intensional treatment of and has to define an intension; that is, for every world, it has to tell us under what circumstances the conjoined sentence is true in that world, and under what circumstances it is false:
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Exercise 2: Compositional Semantics |
  |
A small compositional semantics. The exercise is in the section labeled "Exercise". |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Summarizing |   |
|